geopro:pedro:games
Diferenças
Aqui você vê as diferenças entre duas revisões dessa página.
Ambos lados da revisão anteriorRevisão anteriorPróxima revisão | Revisão anterior | ||
geopro:pedro:games [2008/02/26 17:11] – 150.163.67.167 | geopro:pedro:games [2012/02/16 20:00] (atual) – pedro | ||
---|---|---|---|
Linha 1: | Linha 1: | ||
- | ====== | + | ====== Games ====== |
+ | ==== Braess' | ||
+ | |||
+ | Braess' | ||
+ | The paradox is stated as follows: "For each point of a road network, let there be given the number of cars starting from it, and the destination of the cars. Under these conditions one wishes to estimate the distribution of traffic flow. Whether one street is preferable to another depends not only on the quality of the road, but also on the density of the flow. If every driver takes the path that looks most favorable to him, the resultant running times need not be minimal. Furthermore, | ||
+ | |||
+ | ====Schelling point==== | ||
+ | |||
+ | In game theory, a Schelling point (also called focal point) is a solution that people will tend to use in the absence of communication, | ||
====Game Theory: Dominance, Nash Equilibrium, | ====Game Theory: Dominance, Nash Equilibrium, | ||
- | |B. L. Slantchev, 2007| | + | |B. L. Slantchev, 2007| {{http:// |
That is, we must be able to assume not only that all players are rational, but also | That is, we must be able to assume not only that all players are rational, but also | ||
Linha 13: | Linha 21: | ||
Five Interpretations of Mixed Strategies: | Five Interpretations of Mixed Strategies: | ||
- | - **Deliberate Randomization: | + | - **Deliberate Randomization: |
* the notion of mixed strategy equilibrium does not capture the players’ motivation to introduce randomness into their behavior. This is usually done in order to influence the behavior of other players. We shall rectify some of this once we start working with extensive form games, in which players move can sequentially. | * the notion of mixed strategy equilibrium does not capture the players’ motivation to introduce randomness into their behavior. This is usually done in order to influence the behavior of other players. We shall rectify some of this once we start working with extensive form games, in which players move can sequentially. | ||
* perhaps more troubling, in equilibrium a player is indifferent between his mixed strategy and any other mixture of the strategies in the support of his equilibrium mixed strategies. His equilibrium mixed strategy is only one of many strategies that yield the same expected payoff given the other players’ equilibrium behavior. | * perhaps more troubling, in equilibrium a player is indifferent between his mixed strategy and any other mixture of the strategies in the support of his equilibrium mixed strategies. His equilibrium mixed strategy is only one of many strategies that yield the same expected payoff given the other players’ equilibrium behavior. | ||
- | - **Equilibrium as a Steady State:** players act repeatedly and ignore any strategic link that may exist between successive interactions. In this sense, a mixed strategy represents information that players have about past interactions. For example, if 80% of past play by player 1 involved choosing strategy A and 20% involved choosing strategy B, then these frequencies form the beliefs each player | + | - **Equilibrium as a Steady State:** players act repeatedly and ignore any strategic link that may exist between successive interactions. In this sense, |
- | can form about the future behavior of other players when they are in the role of player 1. Thus, the corresponding belief will be that player 1 plays A with probability .8 and B with probability .2. In equilibrium, | + | - **Pure Strategies in an Extended Game:** Before a player selects an action, he may receive a private signal on which he can base his action. Most importantly, |
- | - **Pure Strategies in an Extended Game:** Before a player selects an action, he may receive a private signal on which he can base his action. Most importantly, | + | - **Pure Strategies in a Perturbed Game:** Harsanyi introduced another interpretation of mixed strategies, according to which a game is a frequently occurring situation, in which players’ preferences are subject to small random perturbations. Like in the previous section, random factors are introduced, but here they affect the payoffs. Each player observes his own preferences but not that of other players. The mixed strategy equilibrium is a summary of the frequencies with which the players choose their actions over time. Establishing this result requires knowledge of Bayesian Games, which we shall obtain later in the course. Harsanyi’s result is so elegant because even if no player makes any effort to use his pure strategies with the required probabilities, |
- | The problem with this interpretation is that it is hard to accept the notion that players deliberately make choices depending on factors that do not affect the payoffs. However, since in a mixed strategy equilibrium a player is indifferent among his pure strategies in the support of the mixed strategy, it may make sense to pick one because of mood. | + | - **Beliefs: |
- | - **Pure Strategies in a Perturbed Game:** | + | |
- | Harsanyi introduced another interpretation of mixed strategies, according to which a game is a frequently occurring situation, in which players’ preferences are subject to small random perturbations. Like in the previous section, random factors are introduced, but here they affect the payoffs. Each player observes his own preferences but not that of other players. The mixed strategy equilibrium is a summary of the frequencies with which the players choose their actions over time. Establishing this result requires knowledge of Bayesian Games, which we shall obtain later in the course. Harsanyi’s result is so elegant because even if no player makes any effort to | + | |
- | use his pure strategies with the required probabilities, | + | ====The Economics of Fair Play==== |
- | - **Beliefs: | + | |K. Sigmund and E. Fehr and M. A. Nowak, 2002| Scientific American| |
- | all other players about this player’s strategies. Here, each player chooses a single strategy, not a mixed one. An equilibrium is a steady state of beliefs, not actions. This interpretation | + | |
- | is the one we used when we defined MSNE in terms of best responses. The problem here is | + | one round ultimatum game. game of the " |
- | that each player chooses an action that is a best response to equilibrium beliefs. The set of | + | |
- | these best responses includes every strategy in the support of the equilibrium mixed strategy | + | If, for instance, the proposer is chosen not by a flip of a coin but |
- | (a problem similar to the one in the first interpretation). | + | by better performance on a quiz, then offers are routinely a bit lower and get |
+ | accepted more easily — the inequality is felt to be justified. | ||
+ | |||
+ | our emotional apparatus has been shaped by millions of years of living in small groups, where | ||
+ | it is hard to keep secrets. Our emotions are thus not finely tuned to interactions | ||
+ | occurring under strict anonymity. We expect that our friends, colleagues and | ||
+ | neighbors will notice our decisions. If others know that I am content | ||
+ | with a small share, they are likely to make me low offers. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Because one-shot interactions were rare during human evolution, these emotions | ||
+ | do not discriminate between one-shot and repeated interactions. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | ====The Power of Memes==== | ||
+ | |S. Blackmore, 2000| | ||
+ | |||
+ | ver URGENTE: colocar na apresentacao para o referata: | ||
+ | "an evolution of ideas, or memes" | ||
Linha 198: | Linha 223: | ||
|Nowak and Sigmund, 1992| Nature| | |Nowak and Sigmund, 1992| Nature| | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | ====The Work of John Nash in Game Theory==== | ||
+ | |H. W. Kuhn, J. C. Harsanyi, R. Selten, J. W. Weibull, E. van Damme, J. F. Nash, P. Hammerstein, | ||
+ | |||
+ | A Nash equilibrium is defined as a strategy combination with the property | ||
+ | that every player’s strategy is a best reply to the other players’ strategies. | ||
+ | **This of course is true also for Nash equilibria in mixed strategies. But in the | ||
+ | latter case, besides his mixed equilibrium strategy, each player will also have | ||
+ | infinitely many alternative strategies that are his best replies to the other players’ | ||
+ | strategies. This will make such equilibria potentially unstable.** | ||
+ | In view of this fact, I felt it was desirable to show that “almost all” | ||
+ | Nash equilibria can be interpreted as strict equilibria in pure strategies of a | ||
+ | suitably chosen game with randomly fluctuating payoff functions. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | ====Non-Cooperative Games==== | ||
+ | |J Nash, 1950| [[http:// | ||
+ | |||
+ | It is assumed that each participant acts independently, | ||
+ | with any of the others. | ||
+ | |||
+ | If we transform the payoff functions linearly: p_i' = a_i p_i + b_i, where a_i > 0, the game | ||
+ | will be essentially the same. Note that equilibrium points are preserved under such | ||
+ | transformations. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Nash proposed two interpretations for the concept of equilibrium. The first one concerns | ||
+ | extremely rational players, which cannot communicate, | ||
+ | game only once. | ||
+ | |||
+ | We shall now take up the " | ||
+ | solutions have no great significance. It is unnecessary to assume that the participants have full | ||
+ | knowledge of the game, or the ability and inclination to go through any complex reasoning process. | ||
+ | But the participants are supposed to accumulate empirical information on the relative advantages | ||
+ | of the various pure strategies at their disposal. | ||
+ | |||
+ | To be more detailed, we assume that there is a population (in the sense of statistics) of | ||
+ | participants for each position of the game. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | ====Games with Finite Resources==== | ||
+ | {{ http:// | ||
+ | Games with finite resources are two-person zero-sum multistage games defined by Gale (1957) to have the following structure. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Player I's resource set is A = {1, 2, ..., N}. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Player II's resource set is B = {1, 2, ..., N}. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Associated with these resources is an NxN payoff matrix M = (M(i, j)). The game is played in N stages and each player is allowed to use each resource once and only once during these N stages. | ||
geopro/pedro/games.1204045883.txt.gz · Última modificação: 2008/02/26 17:11 por 150.163.67.167